There seems to be a dilemma that has not been addressed much in the literature (a dilemma I have hinted at in the past) that concerns freedom and the deontic appraisals of moral obligation, right, and wrong. The dilemma arises when we combine the hard incompatibilist stance regarding the truth of two doctrines coupled with a wide-spread assumption about control. First, the hard incompatibilist stance on determinism; (HD) if determinism is true then we do not have control over any of our actions. Next, the hard incompatibilist stance regarding indeterminism; (IND) if indeterminism is true then we do not have control over any of our actions. Now if we assume that either determinism or indeterminism is true then it follows that we do not have control over our actions. But, if there is good reason to believe that we need “deontic-grounding control” for deontic evaluations to be justified (as I and others have argued), then it follows that none of our deontic evaluations are justified. One goal in this post is to defend the view that moral statuses such as rightness, wrongness, and obligatoriness require a specific species of control, “deontic-grounding control”
Let’s first consider an obligation. Following Ish Haji, if we assume, as Derk Pereboom and most others do that moral responsibility requires control: if one is morally praiseworthy or blameworthy for an action, one has responsibility-relevant control in performing it, then likewise we can think of OIC as the control principle for moral obligation, if one morally ought to do something, then one can do it. Put another way, if a person morally ought to do something, then one has the freedom to do it; if one has a moral obligation to perform an action, one has obligation-relevant control in performing it (Haji 2012a. pp. 24-26). To see this consider a case like Leroy:
Leroy is a paralyzed man from the waist down, seemingly all alone, enjoying some sun at the edge of the lake in his wheelchair. He notices a young man drowning in the lake. Because of his condition it seems plausible to say that he is not obligated to jump in and save the drowning man. He is not obligated to do so because he cannot do so. If he had the opportunity to save him (i.e. he miraculously regained feeling in his legs) we would say that he was obligated to save him. Therefore, it seems plausible to link obligations to opportunities[1]. Thus we can follow Haji in adopting a central principle OIC, as our control principle for moral obligation:
OIC: S ought to do A only if S can do A.
As Haji has noted, barring no strong reasons to believe otherwise the same freedom requirements that hold for moral obligation should also hold for moral wrong and moral right too[2]. Consider moral wrong in light of this. The corollary of (OIC) for wrongness is:
OICW: If it is wrong for S to do, A, then S can do A.
It also seems fundamental to claim that if something is impermissible then it cannot be obligatory.
Given the assumptions that wrong is equivalent to impermissible and that obligations are subsets of permissible actions then the following principle, OW, seems to hold:
OW: Agent S ought to do A if and only if it is morally wrong for S not to do A.
In fact, Furthermore, it is also true that one ought not to do A if and only if it is wrong to do A. If so, then we may follow Haji in accepting this principle:
“Ought Not” is equivalent to “Wrong” (Equivalence): S ought not do A if and only if it is wrong for S to do A.
Now we may argue as follows. Regarding wrong, if it is wrong for one to do A, then one ought not to do A (from Equivalence). If one ought not to do A, then one can refrain from doing A. So, if it is wrong for one to do A, one can refrain from doing A. But it is also true that if it is wrong for one to do A, one can do A (from OICW). Hence, if it is wrong for one to do A, both one can do A and one can refrain from doing A.
Similarly, regarding obligation, if one ought not to do A, then it is wrong for one to do A. If it is wrong for one to do A, then one can do A. Therefore, if one ought not to do A, then one can do A. But it is also true that if one ought not to do A, then one can refrain from doing A (from OIC). Thus, obligation, just like impermissibility, requires two-way control: the ability to do A and to refrain from doing A.
If obligation and wrong require alternatives, then barring no convincing reasons to believe otherwise, right requires alternatives as well. We may conclude that there is a requirement of alternative possibilities for obligation, right, and wrong.
Thus, if hard incompatibilism rules out two-way control it also rules out the deontic evaluations of moral rightness, wrongness, and obligatoriness. In others words, no act can EVER be morally right, wrong, or obligatory for anyone if hard incompatibilism is true. So contrary to what advocates of hard incompatibilism would have you believe our system of morality would be imperilled without free will (of the variety identified with two-way control).
[1] Ish Haji (2002; 2012) and Chris Franklin (2011a; 2011b) have suggested that the “can” in the ought implies can principle refers to one’s opportunities. This seems right to me.
[2] Haji spends a good deal of time arguing for and responding to objections against the symmetry in freedom requirements of obligation, wrong, and right. See (Haji pp.25-51).
References
Franklin, Christopher. 2011a. ‘Masks, Abilities, and Opportunities: Why the New Dispositionalism Cannot Succeed’, The Modern Schoolman (now Res Philosophica) 88:1&2, 89-103. (Special issue on Free Will and Moral Responsibility)
Franklin, Christopher. 2011b. ‘Farewell to the Luck (and Mind) Argument’, Philosophical Studies 156:2, 199–230.
Haji, Ishtiyaque. 2002. Deontic Morality and Control. OUP
Haji, Ishtiyaque. 2012. Reason’s Debt to Freedom. OUP
Sreejith
November 6, 2013
Hi Justin,
Two points:
(1) You said: “the hard incompatibilist stance regarding indeterminism; (IND) if indeterminism is true then we do not have control over any of our actions”. I am having difficulty to understand the calim that if indeterminsim is true we do not have control over any of our action. If we are not determined, it is more likely that we have controll over our action right?
(2) The last line of the first paragraph begins by saying that “One goal in this chapter is to defend the view…” Note that you are saying “cahpter” instead of “post”. You might want to correct it.
Cheers,
Sreejith
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
November 6, 2013
Fixed. Thanks, Sreejith.
LikeLike
Sreejith
November 6, 2013
You are welcome Justin
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
November 6, 2013
Oh, and to answer your question: indeterminism rules out control on the basis of luck (or so the hard incompatibilist will argue). If things are not determined to be a certain way then our actions are not “up to us” rather they are the result of random events-luck. Another way of saying this is that if indeterminism were true then our actions will be random and randomness disallows us to claim that we have control over our actions. Now, Libertarians will claim that indeterminism does not rule out free will. The dilemma as I have constructed it applies only to hard incompatibilists and not to Libertarians. I hope this was helpful.
LikeLike
Sreejith
November 6, 2013
I see. so indeterminism would say that actions are determined/decided not even by our will/intention. I suppose libertarians can be understood as week indetermism.
LikeLike
Matt Bainbridge
November 8, 2013
Hey Justin,
Another awesome post. Your premises seem right to me but i’m not buying your conclusion as i’m sure you would have guessed of me by now lol. The hard incompatibilist seems to me to admit to this from the start. Maybe yes the harsher moral justice that one who believes in free will would advocate would be imperiled but not the objective morality which i believe is all that would be required. An objective morality + social necessity leaves us with what is needed to maintain a prosperous society and I think that is the goal in the long run of morality.
A Serial Killer’s actions are morally bad because they are detrimental to the prosperity of a society and this is all the justification that is needed to deal with this person in such a way as to prevent future damage to society.
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
November 8, 2013
Hi, Matt.
As always I appreciate your response.
You say that objective morality remains but what aspects specifically? It seems that it is not true that we have moral obligations. It also seems false is that what anyone does anything wrong. What is left for morality if it cannot evaluate or prescribe what one ought to do? What function would it serve? Whatever is left seems PALE in comparison to the system we currently endorse (that some actions are right, wrong and obligatory for people at certain times).
Also, something being morally bad is much different from something being morally wrong…
LikeLike
Matt Bainbridge
November 10, 2013
Hey Justin,
I just can’t seem to shake this feeling that while I agree that moral obligation goes out the window with hard incompatibilism that right and wrong morally speaking would still be in play.
maybe this is because even if we could not do otherwise we can in fact imagine worlds in which different possible actions are taken that would be better or worse and we can say that those actions that are better are morally right and those that are worse are morally wrong. The only thing that seems to be lost is the moral praise and blame that comes with moral obligation.
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
November 12, 2013
Here’s one way to think about moral wrong, Matt. For something to be morally wrong it seems fair to say that one should refrain from doing that thing. One ought to refrain from doing that thing is just another way of saying that moral wrong is really an obligation to refrain from performing something. But if one cannot refrain from doing that thing, and, as you agreed moral obligation seems to go then it seems moral wrong goes as well. Has Jonny wronged someone or something if wrong is simply an obligation to refrain? Think about what it would mean to say Jonny did X. X was wrong for Jonny but Jonny could not do otherwise. We can’t say to Jonny that he should not have done what he did if he could not refrain from doing it. And if we can’t say that it seems we can’t say what Jonny did was wrong. It might be bad in the sense that the world is worse off because of it but Johnny did nothing “wrong” per say.
Now, I agree that worlds can be better or worse depending on which actions make up that world but the agents in that world would not be doing “wrong” if there was no ability to do otherwise. I am now researching if in fact it could be the case that we ought to reject hard incompatibilism (HI) in favor of libertarianism because of all that is lost in accepting hard incompatibilism. As long as libertarianism is on the table it seems that it should be selected over (HI) given that the stakes of accepting (HI) seem so high.
That’s a completely different topic and I’m not sure how far I’ll get with that with so much else on my plate but hopefully you get the idea.
LikeLike
mutualrespect23
December 11, 2013
Those mentioned mid paragraph are concerned with being right instead of “Getting it right.” That is the nail on the head people would agree upon. A double minded man is unstable in all his ways, so stop arranging deck chairs on the titanic!
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
December 12, 2013
I’m not sure who you are referring to. Which paragraph, etc?
LikeLike
oliviamariecasey
January 13, 2014
Hi Justin!
I am an undergraduate student of philosophy. I liked your post alot but was confused by the logic at first. So I just wrote my own article response to this article to work it out in my head. I break down your post down into the bare argument. I still logically reconstruct the argument but not as at great depth as you did.
I would be interested to hear your feedback if I understood and evaluated the argument correctly. My post is quite short. If it interests you, here’s the link: http://caseyoliviamarie.wordpress.com/2014/01/13/without-freedom-no-morality-on-the-compatibility-of-theories-of-freedom-and-theories-of-ethics/.
Otherwise, no worries.
Ofcourse, I have included links and credit to you and Haji, I mostly just reconstruct the argument in words that make the most sense to myself.
Thanks for the great article!
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
January 16, 2014
You have done a fine job, Olivia. Thanks for digging into some of my stuff. I’m glad you found it interesting.
LikeLike
Olivia Casey
January 17, 2014
Thank you. Looking forward to keeping up with this blog, it all looks great.
LikeLike
trueandreasonable
January 15, 2014
I came to this blog through Oliviamariecasey’s blog.
I always just sort of assumed your conclusion was true. It comes up in theology when certain Christians will say things like “it is all God” that saves us and nothing we do. It always seemed to me that, if that is the case, then God is really just judging himself.
But the reason I am posting is because i want to run this line of thought by you. The reason I never really studied or inquired much about whether there is a free will is because I am not sure what I would take away from it. I think we should always go on the assumption that we have free will. Because if that assumption is false, there is nothing I could have done anyway.
I am suggesting that maybe there is a principle of rationality that we shouldn’t worry about things that are outside our control. If that is the case then the only possible worlds that we need to worry about anything are the worlds where free will exists.
What do you think?
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
January 16, 2014
I like not worrying about things I can’t control, it alleviates lots of unwarranted stress. I also like to be justified in acting one way or another, and, if we don’t have free will then I may not be justified. I may not be to blame, but I would like to think I am justified in acting a certain way, at least some of the time.
I am not a free will skeptic, I think we have free will, however, my work has been focused on those who think we don’t. If what they say is true then most of our practices are not sufficiently justified. And, though I don’t like worrying about things I can’t control I equally don’t like others telling me what to do (especially if they are not justified). Hopefully, that makes some sense.
LikeLike
trueandreasonable
January 17, 2014
Yes Justin Caouette what you say makes sense thanks for you responses. I still have some questions. I take it then you did not think what I said justified believing in free will, and think some other analysis is necessary to justifiably believe it or justifiably act based on the belief that we have free will?
Its not really a matter of like or dislike. To the extent I did study and think about whether we have a free will I did like it. I just came to the conclusion that a rational person will just always assume they have free will. In your post you say “If what they [people who believe we have no free will] say is true then most of our practices are not sufficiently justified.” I am not sure how that would work. So I am thinking you have some ideas of how that could be, that I don’t.
In Olivia’s blog an issue came up whether holding certain beliefs or not holding certain beliefs is a morally relevant concern. Some people like William Clifford seemed to think it was.
You say:
“I also like to be justified in acting one way or another, and, if we don’t have free will then I may not be justified. I may not be to blame, but I would like to think I am justified in acting a certain way, at least some of the time.”
I was talking about being justified in beliefs, and you are talking about being justified in actions. I think there is a close correspondence between our beliefs and actions so I don’t really see this as a material difference. But if you do draw an important distinction between saying we are “justified in our beliefs” and “justified in our actions” then what I say may or may not apply to you.
But anyway consider this on the assumption you agree with Clifford that (the act of?) holding justified beliefs is a moral issue:
P1) Holding unjustified beliefs implies blameworthiness.
P2) if there is no free will, no one is blameworthy for anything.
Conclusion: The only way to be unjustified in believing there is free will is if you are unjustified in holding a true belief.
I’m not saying that is impossible. Gettier seemed to show that can happen. In those scenarios the person didn’t seem to be blameworthy for their unjustified true beliefs either. But I am sure we can think of examples of people at least potentially unjustifiably believing true beliefs Joyce uses the example of someone believing the number 7 is prime based on Tasseography.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Tasseography.
So its not impossible that someone might be blameworthy for holding a true belief. But I am not sure believing in free will based on the reasoning of the argument I gave above (or what i said originally) is blameworthy reasoning.
Here is an analogy:
You are out camping and a friend gets bit by a snake. Your friend is dying. You have an antidote for a certain type of snake. Now you are not sure if it is the correct antidote because he didn’t actually get a good look at the snake. If he takes the antidote and its not the right one, it will have no effect for good or bad. In sum if this is not the right antidote you have no control whether he will live or die. Accordingly by giving him the antidote you are sure your actions will be blameless.
On the other hand if its the right antidote you do have control over whether he lives or dies and you would be blameworthy for not giving it to him.
So it seems to me you are clearly justified in believing you have control and acting accordingly i.e., giving him the antidote. Worrying about whether its the right antidote and trying to wrack your brain about what sort of snake it may have been based on the short glance he had or where you are in the woods, seems superfluous. It seems that we don’t need to worry about whether we in fact we have control since the only rational way to go is to assume we do have control and therefore give the antidote.
Do you think that is a valid analogy to whether we should believe in free will or not?
LikeLike
Justin Caouette
January 20, 2014
Hi True, you say, “I am not sure how that would work”, in reference to this quote: “If what they [people who believe we have no free will] say is true then most of our practices are not sufficiently justified.” I have detailed why this is so in the post. For an act to be right or wrong for a person that person must be able to perform or refrain from performing that act.
Regarding your argument I think would deny (P1), this is my reaction at first glance. One could hold an unjustified belief and not be blameworthy if one has no way of having a justified belief. Again, if it is impossible to hold a justified belief because we do not have the ability to control our beliefs (assuming this ability entails some sort control over how we weigh evidence–free will) then I do not see how one can be obligated to only believe justified true beliefs if obligation itself requires two-way control. Also, I should mention that I am not familiar with the work of William Clifford.
Now, there is a large debate on whether justified in believing is different than being justified in acting. I am not familiar enough with the belief literature to say where I stand on this but prima facie it seems plausible to accept doxastic voluntarism. I would suggest this piece http://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/27653700?uid=3739392&uid=2&uid=3737720&uid=4&sid=21103303081757 by Pamela Hieronymi titled “Responsibility for Believing”. Clayton Littlejohn has written a bit on this as have others I could refer you to. Again, I am not versed enough in the literature surrounding justification outside the moral sphere and in the epistemic sphere.
I should add, if I have not yet been clear on this, that someone who claims we have free will is justified. They are justified, among other reasons, because they have free will. I am in line with pragmatic encroachment. The stakes dictate how much evidence you need to claim that you have knowledge or that you are justified in claiming you have knowledge. I see my work as raising the stakes on the belief in free will. If my argument is sound, that the truth of judgments of moral obligation, wrong and right depend on metaphysical free will then the stakes seem pretty high in believing that we do not have free will. Thus, we should reject the claim that we do not have it unless we have overwhelming evidence that we do not.
LikeLike
trueandreasonable
January 23, 2014
Thank you very much for the informational post. Having people who can give you good introductory resources to ideas is a big help. It is amazing how much has been written in philosophy.
I too am only lightly familiar with the issues surrounding doxastic voluntarism. I again tend assume I do and not worry about it if I can’t control it. I suppose I will have to really examine my own view on that at some point. I will likely read that article when I get a chance.
But for now I am going through a few papers on “pragmatic encroachment” which I had never heard of before your post here. Is the bank case the classic example when discussing this issue, or are there other equally well known examples? I have several ideas about what is happening there and I would draw different conclusions than most of the authors I have read so far.
BTW when you say: “If what they [people who believe we have no free will] say is true then most of our practices are not sufficiently justified.” When I said “I am not sure how that would work” meant that I don’t know what practices I would change if I stopped believing in free will. I suppose I would look at God and his Judgment differently. But I am not really sure what other practices I would change. I do agree that the stakes have always seemed to be in favor of believing we have free will.
True story: When I was a young kid I played basketball with another young kid. After he missed a shot he ran to the ball and slapped it and yelled “bad basketball!!” I looked at him expecting him to be smiling or kidding but he was seriously angry. It was odd enough to leave an impression. It seems to me that people who blame things that have no free will, are doing much the same thing.
As far as what it means to believe something i generally just tend to go with the description given by W.V. Quine and J.S. Ullian in their book “The Web of Belief.”
“Let us consider, to begin with. What we are up to when
we believe. Just what are we doing? Nothing in particular.
For all the liveliness of fluctuation of beliefs, believing is
not an activity. It is not like scansion or long division. We
may scan a verse quickly or slowly. We may perform a
division quickly or slowly. We may even be quick or slow
about coming to believe something, and quick or slow
about giving a belief up. But there is nothing quick or slow
about the believing itself; it is not a job to get on with. Nor
is it a fit or mood, like joy or grief or astonishment. It is
not something that we feel while it lasts. Rather, believ
ing is a disposition that can linger latent and unobserved.
It is a disposition to respond in certain ways when the
appropriate issue arises. To believe that Hannibal crossed
the Alps is to be disposed, among other things, to say “Yes”
when asked. To believe that frozen foods will thaw on the
table is to be disposed, among other things, to leave such
foods on the table only when one wants them thawed.
Inculcating a belief is like charging a battery. The bat
tery is thenceforward disposed to give a spark or shock,
when suitably approached, as long as the charge lasts.
Similarly the believer is disposed to respond in character
istic ways, when suitably approached, as long as the belief
lasts. The belief, like the charge, may last long or briefly.
Some beliefs, like the one about Hannibal, we shall proba
bly retain while we live. Some, like our belief in the
dependability of our neighborhood cobbler, we may abandon
tomorrow in the face of adverse evidence. And some,
like the belief that a bird chirped within earshot, will
simply die of unimportance forthwith. The belief that the
cobbler is dependable gives way tomorrow to a contrary
belief, while the belief in the bird is just forgotten. A
disposition has ceased in both cases, though in different
ways.”
It does imply a strong belief to action correlation. Hume might not approve. I talk a bit about that description in my blog but I don’t go into Hume.
http://trueandreasonable.co/2014/01/09/do-you-belieeeeve/
LikeLike